46
Climate change, and the conservation of oceans and some rivers, requires not only individual government action, but international agreement.
160
But national governments disagree on which policies to adopt, and who should bear the costs. Countries’ interests differ according to their stage of economic development, possession and use of natural resources, and vulnerability to the impacts of climate change. The 2015 Paris Agreement made progress: countries would adopt domestic mitigation measures to achieve ‘nationally determined contributions’ to emissions reduction, with the goal of limiting the temperature rise to 1.5°C by the end of the century and avoiding the worst impacts of climate change.
[...]
The problem of climate change is extreme, but far from unique. It is an example of a social dilemma. Social dilemmas occur when people do not take adequate account of the effects of their actions on others, whether these are positive or negative.
[...]
Humanity would be better off emitting less pollution, but if you as an individual decide to cut your consumption or your carbon footprint, you will hardly affect the global levels.
161
Altruistic motivations can help to address social dilemmas—because our altruism means that we care about how our actions affect others—but for global challenges like climate change, altruism will not be sufficient: new government policies will have to be involved.
162
For example, one person’s choice of how much to heat their home will affect everyone’s experience of global climate change.
190
When people engage in a common project—whether pest control, irrigation, or reducing carbon emissions—everyone has something to gain if they cooperate, but also something to lose when others free-ride.
208
Reducing carbon emissions requires much greater changes, across many industries and affecting all members of society. One of the obstacles at the United Nations’ annual climate change negotiations has been disagreement over how to share the costs and benefits of limiting emissions between countries—and in recent years, the heavy costs some countries now face from the effects of past emissions elsewhere. To explore the possible situations facing climate negotiators, we will model them as a game between two large countries, hypothetically labelled China and the US, each considered as if it were a single individual. First, we identify possible equilibria when each country behaves strategically; then we can think about how an agreed outcome might be achieved.
209
Figure 4.23a shows the outcomes of two alternative strategies: Restrict (taking measures to reduce emissions, for example by regulating or taxing the use of fossil fuels) and BAU (continuing with ‘business as usual’). What we can expect to happen depends on the pay-offs in each outcome. The essential features of the problem can be captured using an ordinal scale from Best to Worst: it is the order of the pay-offs, not the size, that matters. Figure 4.23b shows two games, corresponding to different sets of hypothetical pay-offs.
210
If you work out the best responses and find the Nash equilibria in each case, you will realise that these two games are similar to cases we have already analysed. The left-hand one is a prisoners’ dilemma, in which BAU is a dominant strategy for each country, leading to a Bad outcome for both. The game on the right is a coordination game, [...] except that the players would like to coordinate on the same strategy, rather than the opposite one. There are two Nash equilibria: one is the Best outcome, in which both countries restrict emissions. But the Bad outcome in which neither do so is also an equilibrium, and if each country expects the other to choose BAU following their past behaviour, we can predict that they may be stuck in the (BAU, BAU) equilibrium. In each case, negotiation may be able to improve the outcome.
[...]
Figure 4.23c presents a third model. It also shows the players’ best responses, and hypothetical numerical pay-offs indicating the value of each possible outcome to the citizens of each country. The worst outcome for both countries is that both persist with BAU, thereby running a significant risk of human (and many other species’) extinction. The best for each is to continue with BAU and let the other one Restrict. The only way to moderate climate change significantly is for both to Restrict. This is another coordination game with two equilibria, but now [...] there is a conflict of interest between the players. This game is what is termed a hawk–dove game: players can act like an aggressive and selfish Hawk, or a peaceful and sharing Dove. In the climate change version, Doves Restrict and Hawks continue with BAU. The conflict of interest is that each country does better if it plays Hawk while the other plays Dove. It captures a situation that is different from the previous two. Both countries have incentives to avoid catastrophic climate change. But they strongly prefer that the other should bear the costs of reducing emissions: each would like to wait to determine if the other will move first.
211
The Pareto-efficient allocation in which both countries restrict emissions also has the highest joint pay-offs. We can think of this as the best outcome for the world as a whole. But it is not an equilibrium.
Applying the hawk–dove game to climate policy
How do you think the hawk–dove game would be played in reality? Can the conflict of interest be resolved? If one country could commit itself to BAU so that the other was certain that it would not consider any other strategy, then the other would play Restrict to avoid catastrophe. But this is true for both countries. Negotiations are bound to be difficult, since each country would prefer the other to take the lead on restricting carbon emissions. The real climate negotiations are of course more complex—virtually all countries in the world are involved. Pay-offs may be different for these varied players. For example, in 2021 China produced 31% of the world’s total carbon emissions, the US was second with 44% of China’s level, followed by India. On a per-capita basis, China produced 55% of the emissions that the US did, and India produced 13% of US emissions.
211-212
How could the global social dilemma of climate change policy, as represented in this game, be solved? Could the governments of the world simply prohibit or severely limit emissions that contribute to the problem of climate change? This would amount to changing the game by altering available strategies by making BAU illegal. But who would enforce this law? There is no world government that could take a government that violated the law to court (and lock up its head of state!). If the climate change social dilemma is to be addressed, Restrict must be in the interests of each of the parties. Consider the bottom-left corner (China plays BAU, US plays Restrict) equilibrium. If the pay-offs to China for playing Restrict were higher, when that is what the US is doing, then (Restrict, Restrict) might become an equilibrium. Indeed, in the eyes of many climate change scientists and concerned citizens, the aim of global environmental policy is to change the game so that (Restrict, Restrict) becomes a Nash equilibrium.
212
Following the 2015 Paris Agreement, almost all countries submitted individual plans for cutting emissions. Although there is no way that the agreement could be enforced, and these plans are not yet consistent with the goal of limiting the global temperature rise to 1.5°C, it is widely considered as a basis for further international cooperation. The Paris Agreement should:
• allow countries to better understand the costs of restricting emissions
• encourage economic players to innovate in order to further lower the costs
• strengthen norms that reduce the attractiveness of BAU
• establish a base of trust to share some of the costs of Restrict and negotiate more ambitiously in the future.
213
Addressing the challenge of climate change requires understanding conflicting as well as common interests.
214
Game theory—including the hawk–dove game—provides alternative ways of representing the challenge of climate change, and means of addressing it.
504
People throughout the world make decisions resulting in carbon dioxide emissions without considering how their decisions contribute to climate damage.
505
The price of fossil fuels typically reflects the suppliers’ costs of extracting and distributing them, but not the costs of global warming which affect all of us.
525
A country that invests in reducing carbon emissions lowers the risks of climate change for other countries.
527
If one farmer contributes to the cost of an irrigation scheme, or one country takes measures to reduce carbon emissions, all farmers or all countries benefit. The irrigation scheme is a public good for the community where it is located. Reductions in atmospheric CO2 are a global public good.
532
We can define public bads: air pollution, for example, is a bad that affects many people simultaneously. It is non-rival in the sense that one person suffering its effects does not reduce the suffering of the others. Atmospheric CO2 is a global public bad.